Tuesday, 16 December 2014
Capitalism, Liberalism and Despotism – Locke and Hobbes (Part Two of "The State in Economic Theory")
Capitalism,
Liberalism and Despotism – Locke and Hobbes
Classical political theory
assumes that the State is the holistic ethico-political ex-pression and
pro-duct of more fundamental social components that precede the State both historically and analytically. The bourgeois
theory of the State, known as liberalism, shares this vision of the State with
the added ingredient that society itself can be separated into a scientific
economic sphere governed by the “laws
of the market” and “economic value”, on one side, and a political sphere of
public opinion guided by ethical
values, on the other. In other words, if Economics is the bourgeoisie’s
scientific rationalisation of capitalism, then Liberalism constitutes its quintessential
political ideology. Liberalism is the political expression of capitalism in
that it proclaims that it is possible to separate the economic sphere of social
life which is the realm of necessity or “free-dom”, that is, the rigid
constraint of each individual free-dom imposed by the free-doms of others all
understood strictly as “individual freedoms” (the optimal utilisation of
resources made scarce by the insatiable nature of individual self-interest –
whence the dismal science – this is the constraint that founds the
scientificity of capitalist social relations, the Objective Value of
neoclassical economic theory) from the sphere of freedom or public opinion in which individuals can air their most
subjective beliefs, the Subjective or Ethical Values of the liberal public
sphere, without – for that very reason, that is, by reason of the “ideal”
nature of opinions and beliefs – upsetting the politico-technical neutrality of
the State which, again, is founded on the scientificity of Economics, that is
to say, on the liberalist presumption of the scientific workings of the
self-regulating market mechanism.
It is the subjectivity of these
ethical values – their origin in the ideal “freedom of the human will” -, and
the fact that this ethical-moral “freedom” can be founded exclusively on the
objectivity and “scientific” operation of the market mechanism and on the “laws
of Economics” – it is these two factors combined that liberalism can exploit
ideologically to vaunt its unique affinity with democracy. The
central tenet of liberalism is that “democracy” is socially impossible unless
the sphere of economic production and exchange is kept hermetically separate
and protected from the sphere of public opinion with its “irrational”
ethico-moral and religious beliefs! Locke and Constant are the great
theoreticians of liberalism. For Locke, the separation of economic and
political spheres is made possible by the fact that it is possible to assign
individual property rights to resources by means of “individual labour” – by
which Locke means also the labour of others exchanged like any other product of
labour or commodity. Constant goes further by treating liberalism as the social
state that allows the transformation of proprietary antagonism from war to
commerce. In other words, for Constant, commerce, or the Lockean appropriation
of resources on the basis of supposedly “individual” labour, leads not just to
social peace guaranteed by a neutral State, but also to international peace
between nation-states on the basis of the disciplining effect of property and
capital movements between nation-states! This could not be achieved without the
existence of “natural rights” that precede the State.
It is just such a jusnaturalist
position that Hobbes denies steadfastly and intransigently – and one that he
demolishes with the ruthlessness of his logic. The greatness of Hobbes lies
precisely in having demonstrated that a society run strictly along capitalist lines
on the basis of possessive individualism is quite impossible because it will
inevitably descend into civil war – that, pace
Constant, it is not possible for commerce to replace war as a means of
resolving the conflict implicit in commercial transactions (possessive individualism,
private ownership of social resources) either within or without the boundaries
of the nation-State. Auctoritas, non
veritas, facit legem. The essence of laws, says Hobbes, is not their
“content”; it is not the “truth” of their injunction – for the simple reason
that there can be no universal Truth of which the laws are dictates. For Hobbes
as later for Nietzsche, the real essence of the law, its actual “truth”, is the
very fact of its enforcement – the fact that a particular Will is able to impose
it on the subjects to which it applies and who are forced to obey it. It is the
authority of the Sovereign, the actual physical ability to enforce the law that
makes it “law”; it is certainly not the correspondence of the law to an
intersubjective universal human Truth that makes it “the law”. (Wrong therefore are the theses of Leo Strauss and Warrender that claim Hobbes for liberalism. And equally wrong is Macpherson to claim that Locke’s theory of the State is in all analogous to Hobbes’s.)
Hobbes’s political theory,
therefore, contra Habermas, is
clearly not an attempt to scientize politics – because for Hobbes it is quite
impossible to give politics any scientific basis – again, for the simple reason
that there can be no scientific “truth” upon which a hypothetical “ideal
polity” (a Utopia) can be founded. On the contrary, for Hobbes what science
dictates is that politics begins and ends with the authority of the Sovereign.
But this authority is legitimated contractually by the subjects of the common-wealth,
of the State, not because it is the settlement dictated by scientific “truth” –
but rather precisely for the opposite reason (!), that is to say, that science
shows conclusively that no commonwealth or society or State can be founded on
the dictates of science! It is this negative conclusion – the impossibility of
a commonwealth or State that answers to a summum
bonum or Truth – that is the real foundation of the Hobbesian status civilis or State as the supreme
and ultimate endeavour of human beings to escape the otherwise ineluctable
state of civil war, the status naturae
or bellum civium (war of all against
all).
To reinforce his point, Hobbes
distinguishes between laws or rights or moral rules that operate in foro interno – in the sense that each
individual human being may repose credence in them – and the utter
impossibility of applying these individual rules in foro externo by virtue of the fact that these “internal” ethical
rules can never coincide with the “external” objective rule imposed by the
State! The only “rule” or Value that can be agreed upon is the scientific fact
that human beings wish above all to preserve their individual “life” from
violent death at the hands of other human beings. And given the ability of any
one individual human being to threaten the life of any other individual, it is
this metus mortis, this fear of
violent death, which can be the only “scientific” basis of the State. The State
is the deus mortalis in the sense
that its godliness – its omnipotence - is not derived from theological sources
but from the very mortal forces of
human voracity, of human appetite for endless possession. Whereas the old
mediaeval Scholastic theories of the State remained theo-cratic in that the supremacy of the State over its subjects remained
still ethico-moral in nature because of its “patriarchal” analogy to the
Divinity and the Judaeo-Christian family, Hobbes’s theory of the State breaks
radically with all previous political theory by asserting and demonstrating
geometrico-mechanically the absolute primacy of the State in the foundation of
human society. The basis of the State is not rendered “scientific” thereby: or
rather, the State is “scientific” only to the extent that science requires it
to proscribe the Political so as to prevent the otherwise inevitable descent of
humanity into total civil war. (As Leo Strauss put it in reference to Schmitt,
Hobbes theorised a State that put an end to politics understood as the state of
nature, and Schmitt theorises a state of nature that reintroduces politics to
the State. Both Hobbes and Schmitt, moving in opposite directions, theorise the
incompatibility of State and politics.)
It is evident therefore that for
Hobbes there can be no distinction or separation of any sphere of civil life,
including the “economic” sphere, from the existence of the State: for Hobbes,
society and the State are one indivisible entity: there is simply no human
society or natural society or civil society possible outside the State. The
State is a restauratio ab imis fundamentis of human society – a total
constitutional order – founded solely on the ability of the Sovereign to
enforce its decisions (the law). It is equally impossible therefore for a law
to be “natural” and thus to be “just” independently of the State that enforces
it: a conduct is “just” in a State that enforces it, and the very same rule can
be “unjust” in a State that proscribes it. A law can be “right” in one State
and its very opposite can be equally “right” in another State that enforces its
opposite. The “truth” of the law is the authority of the Sovereign, not an
independent and intrinsic Value possessed by or contained in that law.
The same applies of course to
economic “laws” based as they must be on the notion of property (the individual
claim to social resources), individual labours or utility (as the subjective
individual ethical basis for property rights), and exchange (as the foundation
of market prices and commerce). All economic science is based on the “exchange”
of pro-ducts between individuals. But “exchange” implies by definition the
existence of property rights possessed by individuals over the pro-ducts that
they are meant “to exchange”. As we have shown, however, for Hobbes no such
property “rights” can exist outside of the State; and they cannot constitute
therefore an objective scientific basis or an ideal ethical basis for the
science of “economics”. For this very reason, the
To be sure, the analytical
framework of Walrasian equilibrium is also beset with “unscientific”
ethico-political and indeed metaphysical problems. It is hard to imagine, for
instance, a more metaphysical notion
than that of “utility”, which is essential to neoclassical economic theory. Or
indeed even the notions of “individual” and “self-interest” that form the
mechanical elements of equilibrium theory. Yet equilibrium theory, exactly like
Hobbes’s notion of the state of nature or state of civil war, begins with the formal equality of individual market
participants who are unequal or different only in the “endowments” with which they conduct their perfectly competitive
market exchange. Indeed, it could be argued that the differences in “initial
endowments” do not constitute “inequality” given that no two individual human
beings are alike! The central ethico-political assumption of equilibrium theory
is that individual market participants have a legal right to their initial endowments.
Once this initial legal right is accepted, then the entire “settlement” of
equilibrium exchange transactions in accordance with utility schedules is
mathematically determined. The absence of “profit” or “surplus value” in
neoclassical equilibrium theory means that the problem of the Dynamik, that is, the problem of the
mutation or trans-formation of the economic system, of its “evolution”, is not
even posed.
Just as in Hobbes’s theory it is
the necessary (to preserve one’s
life) yet free and rational (free because rational) decision of
individuals to alienate their “free-dom” in exchange for the totalitarian rule of the State, which
establishes civil society and proclaims positive laws, so in equilibrium theory
self-interested individuals are governed “from outside” by the quasi-Euclidean totalitarian axioms of the theory which,
as we saw earlier, transform “economic agents” into the “inert bodies” of
mechanical physics. Just as in Hobbes’s state of nature individuals transfer mechanically their de facto possessions or power to the civil state so that they may
be socially recognized as “legal possessions”, so in equilibrium theory the
“endowments” of individuals are sanctioned axiomatically without any question
being posed about how and with what right they came to acquire
these “initial endowments”.
Neoclassical equilibrium theory is entirely analogous to Hobbesian political
theory in that its “government” is entirely external
to its governed individuals who have entirely alienated their individual
free-doms in the state of nature and therefore acquire their possessions and
formal equality before the law in their contractual society solely and
exclusively from the State. The conflicting “free-doms” of individuals lead
them to agree, on pain of mutually assured destruction (ob metum mortis), to
alienate their individual “free-doms” to the State. Once a State is formed, the
individuals who formed it by contract immediately and irrevocably alienate
their erstwhile free-dom to the State. Because the “government” is mechanically
imposed on its “subjects” – because the contractum
unionis becomes instantly or mechanically a contractum subjectionis – we call this equilibrium state or
political state a “state by (contractual) institution” as distinct from a state
“by (historical) acquisition”.
By contrast, in the case of liberalism
in all its forms, right up to Schumpeter’s political elitarianism and economic Dynamik, given the “indeterminateness of prices” caused by the fact that the economic
system is changing endogenously (“from within” and not “from outside” as
in equilibrium) through the innovative
actions of “economic agents” (Withschafts-subjekte)
and changing “incessantly”, the
question that comes up immediately is not just how initial entitlements or endowments are to be settled between
economic agents, but also how present and
future endowments or entitlements are justified! In other words, the
ethico-political questions raised by the Dynamik
relate not just to the initial
acquisition of property rights, to their transfer from the state of nature to
the civil state – to the reception of natural rights by the civil State -, but
also and especially to the present and
future legal claim over the pricing of all goods and services for exchange
on “the market”. In this case we have a Lockean “state by acquisition”.
The contrast between John Locke’s
political theory and the Hobbesian theory lies centrally in the fact that the
first relies on the existence of “natural rights” possessed by individuals in the
state of nature which are then transferred to and received by the civil state
by agreement or social contract so that they may be protected by the State as a
neutral arbiter. In other words, for Locke, unlike Hobbes, “natural rights”
exist already in the state of nature,
and it is only for protection that individuals contractually acquire a State to
preserve these natural rights from violent acts that would lead to a civil war.
Unlike Hobbes, then, Locke does not believe that the state of nature is a state
of war of all against all in which no “natural rights” can be said to exist,
except for the right to preserve one’s life! As a result, the
It is quite right therefore to
place Hobbes in the illiberal, despotic camp of political theory in the sense
that for him human society, understood as a quintessentially bourgeois society
of possessive individuals, must be despotic even though despotism is the
product of a social contract. By contrast, for Locke, a society that is
established by mutual consent cannot be despotic – and therefore the powers of
the State must be limited to adjudicating over the natural rights of
individuals acquired in the state of nature. It would seem thus that Bobbio’s
remonstrations against Macpherson’s attempt to link Locke and Hobbes as ultimately
“collectivist” promoters of the despotic powers of the State are justified.
Pur prescindendo dal mutamento
avvenuto nelle idee di Locke rispetto al potere del sovrano in materia
religiosa, e restringendoci alla questione del potere in materia economica, nel
secondo trattato la sfera di cose moralmente indifferenti che riguardano la
formazione della proprietà e i rapporti economici, è di dominio esclusivo dell'individuo,
e il corpo politico ne è soltanto a post e non il garante o il custode. Anzi
che essere lo stato padrone assoluto e arbitrario dei beni degli individui
(come in Hobbes), gli individui proprietari, cioè padroni di beni, finiscono
per diventare anche i padroni dello stato. La novità della costruzione lockiana
che ne fa il modello dello stato liberale-borghese è l'individuazione e la
scoperta dello stadio dei rapporti economici tra gli individui precedente allo
stadio delle strutture politiche. Lo stato di natura non è più in Locke uno
stato ipotetico, ma è lo stato in cui si sviluppano i rapporti economici
naturali, e questi rapporti sono naturali per il fatto che si formano e si
consolidano indipenden temente dall'intervento dello stato: il quale, se mai,
ne è l'organo di registrazione e di coordinamento. La regolamentazione di
quella vasta sfera di cose moralmente indifferenti che è costituita dalle
azioni economiche, è affidata agli indi-[116] vidui medesimi, cioè è sottratta
al potere assoluto e arbitrario dello stato. Far passare Locke per un «
collettivista » significa non intendere il significato della sua riforma che
consiste nel porre la sovrastruttura politica al servizio della struttura
economica, nel subordinare il potere politico al potere economico, nell'invertire
insomma i termini del problema quali erano stati posti da Hobbes.
Yet, what Bobbio neglects is the
fact that Locke’s liberalism limits the powers of the State only so far as
natural rights are concerned. But once we enquire about what Locke means by
“natural rights”, we see that these rights all originate in the economic sphere
– they all have to do with property rights. And these property rights are
acquired in a manner that is absolute in the sense that the State is powerless
to interfere with their indefinite acquisition. It is this indefinite extension
of property rights that lends to Locke’s economic foundation of his liberalism
a “scientific” basis that is entirely novel in political theory. (The infinite
repeatability of experiments is, as Leo Strauss has insightfully pointed out,
the most essential criterion for the scientificity of experimental science. See
his lectures on Socrates.) Locke postulates the indefinite acquisition of
property rights by individuals in at least three senses: first, individuals can
accumulate property by purchasing the labour of other individuals; second,
property acquisition is not limited by the satisfaction of individual needs
because of the existence of money as general social wealth (cf. Aristotle); and
finally, property rights are not limited to the natural life of individuals
because the right to inheritance forestalls their reversion to the community.
For these three reasons, given that the acquisitiveness of individuals is
utterly unlimited, it follows inevitably that the State will sooner or later
come to represent and protect the natural rights of the richest members of
society to the detriment of everyone else. As a result, the limits of the
liberal State invoked by Locke are confined merely to the sphere of subjective
beliefs and opinions, whereas in the economic sphere, far from being “liberal”
in a “democratic” or even “consensual” sense, as Bobbio suggests, the Lockean
State becomes utterly despotic as much as the Hobbesian!
Bobbio’s summary of the
distinction between Hobbes’s despotic collectivism and Locke’s despotic
liberalism ought to be etched in gold!
Il giusnaturalismo di Locke, che
è poi tutt'uno col suo liberalismo e con la sua teoria dello stato limitato e
controllato, si esprime principalmente nell'affermare l'esistenza e la bontÃ
d'una società naturale distinta dalla [127] società politica. Poiché la societÃ
naturale è di fatto prevalentemente la rete dei rapporti economici, questo
giusnaturalismo lockiano contiene una teoria del primato dell'economico sul
politico, mentre l'antigiusnaturalismo di Hobbes si risolve nella teoria opposta
del primato del politico sull'economico. Il perno del sistema lockiano è la
teoria della proprietà : orbene, la proprietà è l'istituto fondamentale della
vita economica. La scoperta di Locke, almeno di fronte ai suoi immediati
predecessori, è che la proprietà è un istituto naturale, non civile; il suo assunto
è quello di far retrocedere l'origine della proprietà allo stato di natura. Di
fronte ad Hobbes, che aveva fatto della proprietà un istituto di diritto
positivo, Pufendorf aveva iniziato, ma non condotto sino in fondo, la
retrocessione, facendone un istituto di diritto naturale convenzionale. Solo
Locke riesce, con la sua teoria del lavoro come titolo d'acquisto della
proprietà , riportarla al fondo, cioè all'energia dell'individuo, unico signore
del proprio corpo. Attraverso l'acquisto e lo scambio dei beni i destini
dell'uomo si consumano nella società naturale: quando sorge la società civile
il gioco è già fatto. Non per nulla la ragione principale per cui sorge la
società civile, cioè quella società che ha per iscopo la convivenza pacifica, è
la conservazione della proprietà .
What Bobbio leaves out here,
however, is the fact that the “liberal” separation of economic and political
spheres, given the unlimited scientific
understanding of the operation of the former, inexorably turns the Lockean liberal
State not just into an authoritarian
one (as Bobbio accepts referring to Franz Neumann’s famous distinction between
“the authoritarian and the democratic state” – see Bobbio’s “Liberalism and
Democracy”), though not into a “collectivist” one as suggested by Macpherson,
but indeed above all it turns the Locklear liberal State into one as despotic as anything theorized by Hobbes!
Bobbio separates Locke from Hobbes on the ground of liberalism, which he
perceives to be consensual and not despotic, though it may be authoritarian and
undemocratic. Macpherson instead equiparates Hobbes and Locke on the basis of
their presumed collectivism – which
in reality is appropriate only to the Hobbesian but certainly not to the
Lockean State, whose “collectivist” powers are limited to the economic sphere
of necessity but not to the free sphere of public opinion.
But both Bobbio and Macpherson
forget the embryonically “scientific” nature of the economic institutions that
Locke is the first to theorise. It is the inchoate but embryonically
“scientific”, as against merely ethico-moral, nature of the economic
institutions of capitalism he outlines for the first time that separates
Locke’s economic and political spheres so as to make his theory of the State liberal yet not collectivist, against Macpherson. And yet, at one and the same
time, it is equally this “scientific”, and not merely ethico-moral,
understanding of the economic sphere that renders Locke’s liberalism despotic and not “consensual”, against
Bobbio. Whereas Bobbio errs on the side of “consensualism”, Macpherson errs on
the side of “collectivism”. Both Bobbio and Macpherson underestimate the scientistic aspect of Locke’s embryonic
economic theory – the first because he seems to accept the scientificity of
economic theory as the proper foundation of social consensus (economics as the
scientific account of “spontaneous” social choices), and the latter because he
clearly denies it, overlooking thus the “scientism” of economic theory in
separating economic and political spheres in terms of political praxis – which
is what distinguishes Hobbesian from Lockean despotism. What makes both wrong
is the novel “scientific” nature of the economic theory of capitalist society
based on alienated labour that Locke is the first great bourgeois theoretician
to hypothesise. Thus, although Bobbio is again right to chide Macpherson on
Locke’s presumed theory of “civil society”, on the other hand Macpherson is
quite right to lay emphasis on this potential “scientific” future development
in Locke’s theory of the State that brings him closer to Hobbes’s collectivism.
It is easy to see, thus, on the
basis of this “scientific” self-understanding of liberalism, the close analogy
between the Hobbesian state and Walrasian Statik
equilibrium theory, on one side, and the Lockean State and Schumpeter’s Dynamik, on the other side, from the
perspective of arbitrary initial “endowments”. Schumpeter’s Dynamik resembles the Lockean liberal State in the sense that the
claims laid by entrepreneurs to profits,
by capitalists to interest, and by
workers to wages, as well as by
landlords to rent, are based entirely
on ethico-political grounds – “natural rights” - and not on an axiomatic
mechanical exchange derived from the logico-mathematical matching of given individual utility schedules, as
in Hobbes! Unlike the Walrasian Statik,
in the Schumpeterian Dynamik nothing
is “given” – there are no “data” –
because everything is “acquired” ethico-politically by virtue of the “actions”
of economic agents – Schumpeter’s Wirthschafts-subjekte
– who are no longer the unconscious inert
bodies of equilibrium theory but are rather free and creative individuals whose innovative acts enliven an incessantly
changing and mutating economic
system.
Yet, paradoxically, once the
Lockean ethico-moral claim to initial endowments is accepted, then unlike the
Hobbesian theory that always assumes the arbitrariness of Walrasian equilibrium
exchange, the Lockean one thoroughly denies this arbitrariness precisely on the
“scientific” ground of the spontaneous “naturalness” of the property rights
with which the economic agents can continue to exchange not just in a static
equilibrium but also in a dynamic one! In
Locke, the “consensual” character of bourgeois society provides the foundation
for what will become the utilitarian “science of choice” of neoclassical
economics. (Cf. on this, Hayek’s analogous
oxymoronic notion of “spontaneous order” or catallaxy.)
In Hobbes, who is the archetype of bourgeois social and economic
“science”, we find the positive “scientific hypothesis” or rationale provided by the framework of equilibrium whereby the
capitalist system can be ana-lysed as a “balance of competitive and conflicting
forces” whose ultima ratio is that metus mortis (fear of death) that pushes
atomic self-interested individuals out of the status naturae (state of nature), out of its stasis (civil war), and out of its “gravitational centre” or
equilibrium, into the metabolic orbit
of the political convention or status
civilis (civil society). The conflict of the Hobbesian state of nature is
transformed into entrepreneurial activity under the protection of the State.
But under this commercial “continuation of civil war by other means”
(Constant), an ethical or political or rational-efficient productive-scientific
rationale must be found for the determination of prices (for the theory of
distribution) – considering the “separation” between “worker/product” and
employer/worker/product.
Thus, liberalism from Locke onwards hypothesizes the jusnaturalist
“political convention” or rationalization
of the status civilis (civil society)
that takes into account the political and bureaucratic “frictions and fictions”
and compromises, the conventions and atavisms, all guaranteed by the liberal negative State or “Common-wealth”. But
unlike Hobbes, Locke and Constant and Mill do not consider that the liberal
“night-watchman State” or “police State” can never overcome the conflict that
gnaws at the very foundation of bourgeois capitalist society and that must
ultimately drive the political system back
into the paralysis, stagnation or sclerosis and finally the stasis (civil war) of the Hobbesian status naturae. Thus, Lockean liberal
jusnaturalism and Hobbesian despotic positivism become Janus-faced or enigmatic
concepts, the one entering the other as it exits itself. The profit-seeking of
pure competition (jusnaturalism) provides the dynamism of capitalist society
and drives it out of equilibrium; but the profit-making of imperfect
competition (positivism) pulls back into the staticity of equilibrium. The tendency here is toward “entropy” or
paralysis – due to the proliferation of protective measures and to the easier
reliance on conservatism – leading to civil war (stasis or bellum civium).
Monday, 8 December 2014
Coming Soon....
I am dedicating a long study here to "the role of the State in economic theory" that seeks to reconstruct the theoretical origins of the "bourgeois" separation of "public" and "private" - that is, the reduction of what is inevitably the organic division of "social labour" to the "contractualism" of the marketplace society that has become the fallacious locus of "economic science". All friends who are interested are invited to read the first instalment (from Aristotle to Hobbes), with the second on liberalism (Locke and Constant) and its extreme confutation by Hobbes and then Hegel coming next. Essentially. my thesis is that just as there are no "individual labours" but only "social labour", so the State does not emerge (organically or mechanically) from a mythical-hypothetical "civil society" as is envisaged by the liberal creed. Rather, it is the State itself (Weber's centralised use of violence) that channels social resources and utilises "crises" with the aim of preserving the established order - and in the process "trans-forming" it from the institutions of Absolutism to those of "parliamentary liberal democracy".
Of course, this is not to say that the State does this unilaterally: but its trans-formations serve only to perpetuate social antagonism precisely by reducing "social labour" to a contractual morass of "individual labours".It is the impossibility of countering the growing "socialisation" of human needs at the planetary level by means of "contractual" remedies that poses the ultimate barrier to the reproduction of capitalist rule.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)